Behavioral finance models often rely on a concept of individual
investors who are prone to judgment and decision-making errors.
the most common behavior that most investors do when making
investment decision are (which undermine the assumption of
traditional finance)
(1) Investors often do not participate in all asset and security
categories,
(2) Individual investors exhibit loss-averse behavior,
(3) Investors use past performance as an indicator of future
performance in stock purchase decisions,
(4) Investors trade too aggressively,
(5) Investors behave on status quo,
(6) Investors do not always form efficient portfolios,
(7) Investors behave parallel to each other, and
(8) Investors are influenced by historical high or low trading
stocks.
Traditional Finance focuses on how individuals
should behave. Individuals are considered as being “Rational
Economic Men”. This leads to markets where prices reflect all
available relevant information.
Main limitations of Behavioral Finance is that some testing
within psychology use small or non-representative samples. However,
as you can easily replicate many of the studies, it should make it
easier to prove/disprove. Traditional finance on the other hand,
tries to apply mathematical precision with models that won’t yield
such accuracy.
Some examples of shortcomings of traditional
finance:
- Many economic theories and financial theories such as
CAPMassumes rational investors, according to utility maximization.
People aren’t rational.
- Based on the assumption of rational participants, the efficient
market hypothesis assumes that markets are rational. Markets aren’t
rational.
- CAPM says that high risk yields high return. Beta is the
measure of risk in CAPM. In fact, low risk yields high return.
- Information is a central concept in investing. It’s central in
the sense that, it’s said an investor’s informational advantage can
be the sole reason he or she makes money in the market. More
Information ≠ More Money.
All research programs have limitations, of course. But those of
behavioral finance undermine its purpose: that is, to enhance
understanding of financial markets and investor behavior. Others
have written eloquently on this subject, particularly Daniel Beunza
and David Stark, and John Y. Campbell. What I have to add to this
ongoing debate boils down to two points and their consequences:
- 1. Failure to acknowledge the findings of the allied
social sciences
One of the cardinal laws in scholarship is to acknowledge the work
of others and avoid reinventing the wheel. But when you read works
of behavioral finance, you’d never know that deviations from
rational, self-maximizing behavior are old news in psychology,
political science, sociology and anthropology. Check the references
section of a behavioral finance article or book and see how many
citations from those fields you can find. Chances are, there will
be zero. Behavioral finance scholars generally cite each other, or
work from mainstream economics and finance.
This is particularly strange since so much of contemporary
behavioral finance depends on the contributions of social
psychologists like Daniel Kahneman (a 2002 Nobel laureate for his
work in behavioral finance) and the late Amos Tversky, as well as
much older work by people like Herb Simon, who was a Professor of
Political Science and Industrial Administration at various points
in his career. Simon won the Nobel Prize in economics for work done
half a century ago on “bounded rationality“—a concept closely tied
to many of the key phenomena examined by behavioral finance, but
which is virtually ignored in their publications.
While a lot of academic research speaks to a rather small group of
other academics, behavioral finance is distinctive within the
social sciences for restricting its scholarly conversation so
tightly. This isn’t the case in the closely-related disciplines of
economic sociology, neo-institutionalist political science, and
economic anthropology, all of which regularly cite and engage with
one another, to the enrichment of all.
In the case of behavioral finance, reluctance to acknowledge the
many research interests it shares with the allied social sciences
may be part of the larger project of rigid separation and boundary
enforcement that has been carried out by economists since the time
of Pareto. This has created what Schumpeter described as a regime
of “mutual vituperation” which has kept economics and finance in a
state of self-imposed incommunicado with sociology,
limiting the advancement of knowledge on our shared interests.
Behavioral finance, it seems, is sticking to the party line on this
point.
- 2. A narrow, limited critique of economic
theory
Cataloging the many ways humans fail to think rationally about
money, investments and risk is a good start. But in most ways,
behavioral finance leaves intact the problematic assumptions of
traditional finance, pulling its punches, so to speak. Among the
most noteworthy examples:
- a. Behavioral finance remains stuck at the individual level
of analysis
As in traditional finance and economics, the object of inquiry in
behavioral finance is the individual—despite rafts of evidence
going back decades that individuals don’t make decisions about
money, risk or investing in a vacuum, but as a result of social
influences. Of course, this evidence comes from those allied social
sciences that are being so studiously ignored. For example,
economic psychologist George Katona showed 35 years ago that most
people choose investments based on word of mouth recommendations
from their friends and neighbors. This influence of social forces
in economic decision-making has been demonstrated with equal or
greater impact among finance professionals—for instance, in a study
of Wall Street pension fund managers by economic anthropologists
O’Barr and Conley, and more recently in a sociological study of
arbitrage traders by Beunza and Stark.
In the past, there were encouraging signs that behavioral finance
might break through the limitations imposed by sticking to the
individual level of analysis, most strikingly in Robert Shiller’s
1993 statement that “Investing in speculative assets is a social
activity.” But thus far, the implications of such statements, and
the plethora of evidence supporting them, remain unexplored.
- b. Behavioral finance limits itself to pointing out
failures of cognition and calculation
As important as those factors are in distorting financial
decision-making, there are a host of others that we know
about—based on research in those allied social sciences that
behavioral finance doesn’t acknowledge—that are excluded from
research in behavioral finance. This includes emotions, and social
phenomena like status competition, both of which play a significant
role in the findings of economic sociology, psychology and
anthropology. The cognitive/calculative failures may interact with
the socio-emotional phenomena, but we won’t know as long as
behavioral finance pretends the latter don’t exist. That’s a loss
for all of us interested in markets, money and investing.
- c. Behavioral finance doesn’t explain how individual acts
and decisions produce aggregate outcomes
As a consequence of keeping the analytical focus on
individuals—avoiding the social and interactive aspects of economic
activity—behavioral finance doesn’t have the theoretical means to
address mechanisms through which individual acts and decisions
aggregate. That means it can’t explain institutions and other
manifestations of collective behavior which form the context for
all the individual behavior it examines. Of course behavioral
finance can’t answer all questions about money and markets, but it
ought to be able to explain what happens when hundreds, or hundreds
of millions, of people fall prey to the “hot hand” fallacy or
availability bias? If behavioral finance won’t touch questions like
that, who will?
The consequences for ignoring the other social sciences and
mounting a very narrow critique of traditional finance and
economics, include:
- Limited predictive power
Behavioral finance tells us more about what people won’t do (e.g.,
behave according to notions of rationality outlined in economic
theory) than what they will do.
- Contradictory implications
Are investors risk-averse or overconfident? How should we reconcile
seemingly contradictory findings like these? Behavioral finance
doesn’t tell us, because of its…
- Failure to offer a viable alternative to the theories it
challenges
Pointing out all the ways that real life behavior doesn’t bear out
the predictions of traditional economics and finance is
interesting—even fascinating, at times—but it’s not an alternative
theory. “People aren’t rational” isn’t a theory: it’s an empirical
observation. An alternative theory would need to offer an
explanation, including causal processes, underlying mechanisms and
testable propositions.
All this keeps behavioral finance dependent on traditional
economics and finance rather than allowing it to grow into a robust
theoretical realm in its own right. Perhaps someday the field will
develop into something more truly challenging to economic
orthodoxy. Until then, behavioral finance will have to play Statler
and Waldorf to the Muppet Show of mainstream
finance—providing entertaining critique, but not replacing the
marquee acts